The 1950s, 60s, and 70s - les trentes glorieuses, the French call
them - were indeed fat years in Western Europe and the United States. Unions
were strong, unemployment was low, and a lot of jobs still came with health
insurance, pensions, and a fair chance of not either migrating at any moment to
lower-wage countries or suddenly being replaced by software/hardware.
Notwithstanding an ugly racist backlash to the Civil Rights Movement and an
unjust, hideously destructive war in Indochina, it was possible, for a few
brief years, to believe that the American economy and polity were sound in
their fundamentals, however much in need of reform.
And yet, radical social criticism
flourished in those decades as never before in America, not even in the Great
Depression: Mills, Marcuse, Goodman, Baldwin, Harrington, Lasch, Kozol, Norman
O. Brown, Wendell Berry, Shulamith Firestone, the Port Huron Statement, among
others. Perhaps there's something to the idea that revolutions are a response
to rising expectations: that economic success and apparent security liberate
the radical imagination, while widespread insecurity cramps it, inducing a
defensive crouch. At any rate, an awful lot of people back then professed
themselves - ourselves, I must acknowledge sheepishly - revolutionaries.
Ivan Illich was an idiosyncratic
revolutionary. Fundamentally, most radical critics object that our institutions
unfairly allocate good and services - education, health care, housing,
transportation, consumer goods - or jobs, or respect, or, simply, money. Illich
nicely summarized the left's perennial program as "more jobs, equal pay for
equal jobs, and more pay for every job." For Illich, these demands were beside
the point. He thought that, by and large, the goods, services, jobs, and rights
on offer in every modern society were not worth a damn to begin with. In fact,
he thought they, and the way of life they constituted, were toxic. He was not a
reactionary in any useful sense of that term, but he was a fervent
anti-progressive.
Illich was born in Vienna in 1926 of
Jewish and Catholic parents. The family fled the Nazis in 1941, and after the
war, Illich studied cell biology and crystallography in Florence, theology and
philosophy in Rome, and medieval history in Germany. He was ordained a Roman
Catholic priest and in 1951 was sent to a poor Puerto Rican parish in New York
City. He was very successful, both as a parish priest and also, somewhat more
surprisingly, in charming the ultra-conservative Cardinal Spellman. In 1956 he
became vice-rector of the Catholic University of Puerto Rico. By then he was a
fairly outspoken critic of pre-Vatican II Catholic orthodoxy, and his new
superiors were not charmed. He spent 1959 wandering around Latin America, then
settled in Cuernavaca, Mexico, where he founded a freewheeling language school
and research center, the Center for Intercultural Documentation (CIDOC), which
became, like Berkeley and Greenwich Village, a seedbed of Sixties radicalism.
At some point the Vatican became
alarmed - it's rumored that the CIA had complained about him - and Illich was
summoned to Rome to explain himself. Apparently the Church authorities
satisfied themselves that this retiring polyglot cleric was not actively
subversive. But CIDOC had become a distraction, as had his own growing
celebrity. Illich had no taste for empire-building, so he phased out the Center
in 1976 and became an itinerant scholar, living from course to lecture series to
research grant, with occasional royalties as well. He wrote a dozen books (or
fifteen, depending on how strict your definition is) and died in 2002.
The first of Illich's books, Deschooling Society (1971), made him
very famous. It caught the crest of a wave of critique and experiment in
American education: Paul Goodman, John Holt, Paulo Freire, free schools,
community control. Illich shared his contemporaries' anti-authoritarianism but
not their reasons. For most educational radicals, the enemies were tradition -
the age-old authority of church and state, bosses and parents - and inequality
- the gap between resources devoted to rich and poor children. From this point
of view, the remedies were plain: practice emancipatory social relations in all
schools and lavish more resources on those serving poorer children.
To Illich's mind, those remedies
missed the point. He thought the educational system had no good reason to exist.
It was, like every modern service industry, in the business of creating and
defining the needs it purported to satisfy - in this case, certification as an
expert - while discrediting alternative, usually traditional, methods of
self-cultivation and self-care. The schools' primary mission was to produce
people able and willing to inhabit a historically new way of life, as clients
or administrators of systems whose self-perpetuation was their overriding goal.
Thus schools produce childhood, a phenomenon that is, Illich claimed, no more
than a few centuries old but is now the universal rationale for imposing an
array of requirements, educational and medical, on parents and for training people
as lifelong candidates for credentials and consumers of expertise.
It is not what schools taught that Illich objected to; it is that they taught:
To
understand what it means to deschool society, and not just to reform the
educational establishment, we must focus on the hidden curriculum of schooling.
... [It is] the ceremonial or ritual of schooling itself [that] constitutes such
a hidden curriculum. Even the best of teachers cannot entirely protect his
pupils from it. Inevitably, this hidden curriculum of schooling adds prejudice
and guilt to the discrimination which a society practices against some of its
members and compounds the privilege of others with a new title to condescend to
the majority. Just as inevitably, this hidden curriculum serves as a ritual of
initiation into a growth-oriented consumer society for rich and poor alike.
Once
young people have allowed their imaginations to be formed by curricular
instruction, they are conditioned to institutional planning of every sort. ...
Neither ideological criticism nor social action can bring about a new society.
Only disenchantment with and detachment from the central social ritual and
reform of that ritual can bring about radical change.
What school teaches, first and last,
is "the need to be taught."
In a series of subsequent books - Tools for Conviviality (1973), Energy and Equity (1974), Medical Nemesis (1975), Toward a History of Needs (1978), The Right to Useful Unemployment (1978),
and Shadow Work (1981) - Illich
formulated parallel critiques of medicine, transportation, law, psychotherapy,
the media, and other social spheres. The medical system produces patients; the
legal system produces clients; the entertainment system produces audiences; and
the transportation system produces commuters (whose average speed across a city,
he liked to point out, is less than the average speed of pedestrians or
bicyclists - or would be, if walking or bicycling those routes hadn't been made
impossible by the construction of highways). In this process, far more
important than merely teaching us behavior is the way these systems teach us
how to define our needs. "As production costs decrease in rich nations, there
is an increasing concentration of both capital and labor in the vast enterprise
of equipping man for disciplined consumption."
Why do we have to be taught to need
or disciplined to consume? Because being schooled, transported, entertained,
etc. - consuming a service dispensed by someone licensed to provide it - is a
radical novelty in the life of humankind. Until the advent of modernity only a
century or two ago (in most of the world, that is; longer in "advanced"
regions), the default settings of human nature included autonomy, mutuality,
locality, immediacy, and satiety. Rather than being compulsorily enrolled in
age-specific and otherwise highly differentiated institutions, one discovered
interests, pursued them, and found others (or not) to learn with and from. Sick
care was home- and family-based, far less rigorous and intrusive, and suffering
and death were regarded as contingencies to be endured rather than pathologies
to be stamped out. Culture and entertainment were less abundant and variegated
but more participatory. The (commercially convenient) idea that human needs and
wants could expand without limit, that self-creation was an endless project,
had not yet been discovered.
This is perhaps obvious; but can
Illich seriously doubt that the great changes since then constitute progress?
It's a question to which he cannily declined to give a direct answer, even while
he assailed the self-satisfaction of the age. He insisted that he was a
historian and diagnostician, not an advocate or a prophet. He at any rate
fleshed out the diagnosis amply and eloquently, especially in Medical Nemesis, his longest book. "The
pain, dysfunction, disability, and anguish resulting from technical medical
intervention rival the morbidity due to traffic and industrial accidents and
even war-related activities, and make the impact of medicine one of the most
rapidly spreading epidemics of our time." Partly this was malpractice, or what
he called "clinical iatrogenesis": "The Department of Health, Education, and
Welfare calculates that 7 percent of all patients suffer compensable injuries
when hospitalized. ... One out of every five patients admitted to a typical
research hospital acquires a iatrogenic disease. ... The frequency of reported
accidents in hospitals is higher than in all industries except mines and
high-rise construction." But these defects were reformable; more intractable
was "cultural iatrogenesis": the destruction of "the potential of people to
deal with their human weakness, vulnerability, and uniqueness in a personal and
autonomous way." The difficulty of giving birth or dying at home is an obvious
example.
Even more fundamental was "social
iatrogenesis," the damage that results from the institutional shape medicine
takes in modern society. "When the intensity of biomedical intervention crosses
a critical threshold, clinical iatrogenesis turns from error, accident, or
fault into an incurable perversion of medical practice. In the same way, when
professional autonomy degenerates into a radical monopoly and people are
rendered impotent to cope with their milieu, social iatrogenesis becomes the
main product of the medical organization."
The notion of "radical monopoly" plays an important role in Illich's
critique of professionalism:
A radical monopoly goes deeper than that of any one
corporation or any one government. It can take many forms. When cities are
built around vehicles, they devalue human feet; when schools preempt learning,
they devalue the autodidact; when hospitals draft all those who are in critical
condition, they impose on society a new form of dying. Ordinary monopolies
corner the market; radical monopolies disable people from doing or making things
on their own. The commercial monopoly restricts the flow of commodities; the
more insidious social monopoly paralyzes the output of nonmarketable
use-values. Radical monopolies ... impose a society-wide substitution of
commodities for use-values by reshaping the milieu and by "appropriating" those
of its general characteristics which enabled people so far to cope on their
own.
Professions
colonize our imaginations; or as Foucault (whom Illich's language sometimes
recalls - or anticipates) might have said, they reduce us to terms in a
discourse whose sovereignty we have no idea how to contest or criticize.
Unlike Foucault, who sometimes seemed to take a grim satisfaction in demonstrating
how cunningly we were imprisoned in our language and institutions, Illich was
an unashamed humanist. His ties to the barrios
and campesinos of North and South
America were deep and abiding. His
"preferential option for the poor" (the slogan of Catholic liberation theology)
was a peculiar one: he hoped to save them from economic development at the
hands of Western-trained technocrats. Illich had hard words for even the best
Western intentions toward the Third World. (It is possible that what annoyed
the CIA was Illich's advice to the Peace Corps volunteers who came to Cuernavaca
for Spanish-language instruction that they should leave Latin American peasants
alone, or perhaps even try to learn from them how to de-develop their own
societies.) Religious and ecological radicals, however generous and respectful,
still wanted to bring the poor a poisoned gift.
Development has had the same effect in all societies:
everyone has been enmeshed in a new web of dependence on commodities that flow
out of the same kind of machines factories, clinics, television studios, think
tanks. ... Even those who worry about the loss of cultural and genetic variety,
or about the multiplication of long-impact isotopes, do not advert to the
irreversible depletion of skills, stories, and senses of form. And this
progressive substitution of industrial goods and services for useful but
nonmarketable values has been the shared goal of political factions and regimes
otherwise violently opposed to one another.
Illich might have said more about those fugitive "stories, skills, and
senses of form"; he might have tried harder to sketch in the details of a
society based on "nonmarketable values." But in Tools for Conviviality and elsewhere, he at least dropped hints. He
certainly did not idealize the primitive - he might have welcomed the term
"appropriate technology" if he had encountered it. He enthused over bicycles
and the slow trucks and vans that moved people and livestock over the back
roads of Latin America before the latter were "improved" into useless and
dangerous highways. He was a connoisseur of the hand-built structures cobbled
together from cast-off materials in the favelas
and slums of the global South. He thought phone trees and computer databases
that would match learners and teachers were a very plausible substitute for the
present educational system. He thought the Chinese "barefoot doctors" were a
promising, though fragile, experiment. He was friendly to any gadget or
technique or practice - he called them "convivial" tools - that encouraged
initiative and self-reliance rather than smothering those qualities by
requiring mass production, certified expertise, or professional supervision.
Illich proposed "a new kind of modern tool kit" - not devised by planners
but worked out through a kind of society-wide consultation that he called
"politics," undoubtedly recognizing that it bore no relation to what currently
goes by that name. The purpose of this process was to frame a conception of the
good life that would "serve as a framework for evaluating man's relation to his
tools." Essential to any feasible conception, Illich assumed, was identifying a
"natural scale" for life's main dimensions. "When an enterprise [or an
institution] grows beyond a certain point on this scale, it first frustrates
the end for which it was originally designed, and then rapidly becomes a threat
to society itself."
A livable society, Illich argued, must rest on an "ethic of austerity."
Of course he didn't mean by "austerity" the deprivation imposed by central
bankers for the sake of "financial stability" and rentier profits. Nor, though
he rejected affluence as an ideal, did he mean asceticism. He meant "limits on
the amount of instrumented [i.e., technical or institutional] power that anyone
may claim, both for his own satisfaction and in the service of others." Instead
of global mass society, he envisioned "many distinct cultures ... each modern and
each emphasizing the dispersed use of modern tools."
Under such protection against disabling affluence ...
tool ownership would lose much of its present power. If bicycles are owned here
by the commune, there by the rider, nothing is changed about the essentially
convivial nature of the bicycle as a tool. Such commodities would still be
produced in large measure by industrial methods, but they would be seen and
evaluated ... as tools that permitted people to generate use-values in
maintaining the subsistence of their respective communities.
Whether one
calls this revolution or devolution, it clearly requires, he acknowledged, "a
Copernican revolution in our perception of values." But there was nothing
quixotic or eccentric about it. On the contrary, this affirmation of limits
aligns Illich with what is perhaps the most significant strain of social
criticism in our time: the anti-modernist radicalism of Lewis Mumford,
Christopher Lasch, and Wendell Berry, among others.
Any assessment of Illich's thought requires at least a footnote about his
curious, controversial late work, Gender
(1983). Like many anti-modernists, Illich had an uneasy relationship with
feminism. He thought about sexual inequality much as he did about economic
inequality: its injustice was too obvious to need much arguing, but more money
and power for women and the poor amounted to, in effect, better seats at the
banquet table when all the food was unhealthy and unpalatable. He was, unlike
most political and sexual radicals, disenchanted with money and power
altogether.
Illich claimed that sex, like childhood, was a modern invention. When
production moved out of the household, life was sundered into two spheres: one
where the means of life were gained, and another which supported those efforts.
Marxists called these two realms the sphere of production and the sphere of
social reproduction. Illich called them wage labor and "shadow work." The
latter included all unpaid efforts that made the former possible: not only
housework, shopping, and child care but also what has come to be called
"emotional labor," and even the family's liaison with external caregivers. The
great majority of this shadow work is done by women, increasingly alongside
their own wage labor. Sex as a role, an attribute of a being abstractly
conceived as a laboring subject, evolved as a rationale for this division into homo economicus and femina domestica, which Illich condemned as heartily as any
feminist could wish.
Before sex, there had been only gender. Every pre-modern society,
according to Illich, assigned every object and every task - and sometimes each
stage of each task - either exclusively to men or exclusively to women. "From
afar, the native can tell whether women or men are at work, even if he cannot
distinguish their figures. The time of year and day, the crop, and the tools
reveal to him who they are. Whether they carry a load on their head or shoulder
will tell him their gender." The specific assignments varied from one society
to another; what never varied was that some activities and objects were only
for women or only for men.
What to do with this historical and anthropological fact - if it is a
fact - was not clear, even to Illich. But he was sure it mattered deeply, and
he tried to say why in a remarkable passage that can serve as well as any to
summarize his view of modern life. (It will help the reader to know that
"vernacular" was a term of art for Illich: it meant "untaught," with overtones
of "colloquial," "customary," "instinctual," and perhaps most usefully,
"amateur.")
The distinction between
vernacular gender and sex role is comparable to that between vernacular speech
and taught mother tongue, between subsistence and economic existence.
Therefore, the fundamental assumptions about the one and the other are
distinct. Vernacular speech, gender, and subsistence are characteristics of a
morphological closure of community life on the assumption, implicit and often
ritually expressed and mythologically represented, that a community, like a
body, cannot outgrow its size. Taught mother tongue, sex, and a life-style
based on the consumption of commodities all rest on the assumption of an open
universe in which scarcity underlies all correlations between needs and means.
Gender implies a complementarity within the world that is fundamental and
closes the world in on "us," however ambiguous and fragile this closure might
be. Sex, on the contrary, implies unlimited openness, a universe in which there
is always more.
Criticism of this breadth and depth illuminates everything. Exactly how
to turn it against everything is usually, as in this case, more than even the
critic can say.
Leave a comment