May 1, 2017
Basic Income: A
Radical Proposal for a Free Society and a Sane Economy by Philippe van
Parijs and Yannick Vanderborght. Harvard University Press, 400 pages, $29.95.
From St.
Paul's venerable saying, "if a man does not work, neither shall he eat," to the
always-contemporary saw, "there's no such thing as a free lunch," the common
sense of humankind has always seemed dead against a universal, unconditional
basic income. Charity, of course, is no less a tradition: for widows, orphans,
and the infirm in all periods, and in the modern period also as social
insurance for the elderly and the involuntarily unemployed.
But aid
for the deserving poor has at times, and especially in modern times, entailed
the expensive and humiliating burden of proving to the satisfaction of donors
that the recipient is indeed both deserving and poor. And even in the most
generous and enlightened societies, such aid has sometimes had perverse
effects. The most common is the "poverty trap." When aid is means-tested, every
dollar of earned income above the qualifying level results in a corresponding
reduction of aid. This is a disincentive to accept the generally low-income,
training-poor jobs available to welfare recipients. The same disincentive
functions as a "household trap," keeping women - the usual caregivers - with
small children at home until the children are grown, insuring that when those
women do eventually enter the labor market, they are at a severe disadvantage.
In the United States, the Clinton administration resolved this dilemma by the
simple, harsh step of eliminating long-term assistance to poor households,
forcing even parents of small children into the labor force - a boon to low-wage
employers. Unemployment insurance, meanwhile, is conditional on recipients'
producing evidence of a minimum number of job applications per week - a
requirement that, as often as not, proves either burdensome or farcical.
We do
not, obviously, take very good care of our poor and unemployed. And we will
soon have even more of them: the elimination of jobs by automation has barely
begun. Without a radical new approach to economic security, we are headed
either for an even worse bureaucratic morass or for a Blade Runner, devil-take-the-hindmost world.
Basic Income by economist Philippe van
Parijs and political scientist Yannick Vanderborght (hereafter V.V.) proposes a
radical idea that will be new to many readers although, as they conscientiously
point out, it has a rich history. Like most good political ideas, the right to
a basic income originated in the Enlightenment, though proposals for the relief
of the poor are of course much older. St. Ambrose waxed eloquently indignant on
the subject of economic inequality. Luther admonished the German nobility that
"it would be easy to make a law, if only we had the courage ... that every city
should provide for its own poor." The narrator of More's Utopia railed against England's savage punishment of crimes against
property: "It would be far more to the point to provide everyone with some
means of livelihood, so that no one is under the frightful necessity of
becoming first a thief, then a corpse."
The philosophes radicalized and
universalized this impulse. According to Montesquieu, the state "owes all its
citizens a secure subsistence"; Rousseau posited that "every man has naturally
a right to everything he needs"; Condorcet wrote that "society is obliged to
secure the subsistence of all its citizens." Tom Paine even proposed the first
universal basic income, combining an endowment at age 21 and a retirement
income at 50. The subsequent history of experiments with income-security
schemes in modern Europe and the United States, from Bismarck to Milton
Friedman, from the Poor Laws to the current experiments in Switzerland, is a
secondary but fascinating theme of Van Parijs and Vanderborght's book.
There
are three defining elements in V.V.'s proposal. First, basic income is individual, paid to each citizen rather
than to a family or household. Second, it is universal, paid without regard to other income or assets. Third, it
is obligation-free, a matter of
right, and not tied to any work requirement. Other aspects of their plan -
income levels, funding mechanisms, pace of adoption - are less fundamental.
The
chief reason for individual rather than household payments is that marriage and
cohabitation are complicated enough without introducing economic incentives into
a relationship. Public assistance programs usually take account of the
economies of scale in consumption that living together entails, reducing
benefits accordingly. But basic income is not a poverty-reduction program; it
is a freedom-maximization program. Its purpose is to increase options for
everyone, in both work life and intimate life.
Why
universality? In the first place, because means-testing is an administrative
nightmare. But even more important, because it frees recipients to work. At
present, earned income reduces public assistance dollar for dollar, and a
full-time job is likely to result in termination of benefits. But far too many
of the jobs available to most recipients of public assistance are insecure
dead-ends. If the jobs disappear or prove intolerable, the resulting interval
until benefits resume can plunge a family into a debt spiral. With a secure
basic income, taking whatever job is available entails no such risk, and
recipients are freer to take a low-paying job that provides valuable training
or experience, hence perhaps a way out of the low-wage ghetto. They are also
freer to create their own jobs, and even to become entrepreneurs, on however
humble a scale.
It is
the obligation-free part that sticks in many people's craw - who, after all, is
not incensed by the spectacle of the idle poor? Forcing recipients of public
assistance to prove that they are involuntarily unemployed serves several
unworthy social purposes: it gratifies popular sadism; it keeps the number of
recipients down; and it swells the reserve army of the unemployed, thereby
subsidizing low-wage employers. V.V. quote a sociologist's scathing description
of the effects of obligation-to-work regulations: by "allowing the authorities
to force someone into a job, however rotten or badly paid," they "assure that
the meanest employer, paying the worst wages for the filthiest jobs, is not
kept out of a worker while there is one able-bodied unemployed man available."
And of course, like means-testing, obligation-to-work regulations require a
large, expensive, and intrusive bureaucracy.
Historically,
the two main grounds for criticizing unbridled competitive individualism have
been efficiency and justice: it wastes the talents of the losers and deprives
them of chances for a decent life. These are also the moral underpinnings of a
universal basic income. V.V. repeatedly stress that their proposal is not a
species of poor relief; it provides a floor, not a safety net. It is not only,
or even primarily, intended to keep people from starving or sleeping in the
streets. Shelters and soup kitchens might achieve that goal equally well, but the
goal itself is too modest. A basic income aims at allowing people to design
their lives, on the principle that while creativity in some form is a universal
biological endowment, chronically insecure, degraded, and exploited people
cannot be creative, and society will be worse off for the loss.
The
argument from justice may, as in Rousseau, appeal to every individual's natural
right to realize her powers, rather than, as in the argument from efficiency, to
society's interest in her doing so. This argument is perfectly adequate,
provided rights are derived from contingent moral intuitions - Smith's and
Hume's "sympathy," for example - rather than from supposedly immutable (but
unfortunately nonexistent) metaphysical principles. But there is another, even
firmer ground for treating basic income as a right: the social nature of wealth
creation. Markets do not allocate rewards fairly; no one deserves to be filthy
rich. V.V. illustrate by quoting the economist and computer scientist Herbert
Simon, one of the 20th century's biggest brains:
When
we compare average incomes in rich nations with those in Third World countries,
we find enormous differences that are surely not due simply to differences in
motivations to earn [or natural resources, but to] differences in social
capital that takes primarily the form of stored knowledge (e.g., technology,
and especially organizational and governmental skills). Exactly the same claim
can be made about the differences in income within any given society. ... It is
hard to conclude that social capital can produce less than about 90 percent of
income in wealthy societies like those of the US or Northwestern Europe. ... [A flat
tax of 70 percent] would generously leave the original recipients of the income
with about three times what, according to my rough guess, they had earned. ... In
the US, a flat tax of 70 percent would support all governmental programs ... and
allow payment, with the remainder, of a patrimony of about $8000 per annum per
inhabitant, or $25000 for a family of three. ... Of course, I am not so naïve as
to believe that my 70 percent tax is politically viable in the US at present [i.e.,
1998], but looking toward the future, it is none too soon to find answers to
the arguments of those who think they have a solid moral right to retain all
the wealth they "earn."
It is, indeed, never too
soon to disturb the ineffable confidence of overpaid blockheads in their
perfect entitlement to a disproportionate share of the common wealth. There
most certainly is such a thing as a free lunch. There is, in fact, a free
banquet, of which every rich person daily partakes. It is long past time they
invited the rest of us.
********************
Much of Basic Income is devoted to practical
matters: in particular, to comparing V.V.'s proposal with likely alternatives.
Traditional guaranteed minimum income schemes involve means-testing, clawback
(the reduction of assistance dollar-for-dollar of earned income), and proof
that the recipient is actively seeking employment, with the undesirable effects
already noted. Those disadvantages have been widely enough recognized that both
liberals and enlightened conservatives
generally prefer a different income-maintenance approach, either a negative
income tax or an earned income tax credit.
The
best-known proponent of a negative income tax was Milton Friedman. As with a
basic income, a minimum income level is set for all individuals or households,
and those with incomes lower than the minimum receive an amount equal to the
difference. By means of a somewhat technical but always clear discussion, V.V.
show that, given certain common features (payment to individuals, no work
requirement, and similar funding mechanisms and tax rates), a negative income
tax and a universal basic income are equivalent in every respect but one. That
respect is, however, crucial. A basic income is paid upfront: weekly, monthly,
or quarterly. A negative income tax is paid out at the end of the tax year; and
as V.V. dryly observe, "poor people cannot wait until the end of the tax year
before receiving the transfer that will enable them not to starve."
An
earned income tax credit (EITC), a variant of the negative income tax, first
introduced in 1975, is now the largest poverty program in the United States.
Its defining feature is that benefits are paid only to the employed. If a
means-tested program is also in place, the EITC would approximate the effects
of a negative income tax, though again without the ability to cushion families
through periods of income deprivation. Without a minimum income program, an
EITC functions as a subsidy to low-wage employers, which doubtless explains its
popularity in the US.
V.V.
also discuss a range of other possibilities: wage subsidies, a reduction of the
work week, the government as employer of last resort, and a close cousin of universal
basic income, a universal lump-sum endowment at age 18 or 21. They argue,
plausibly I think, that in all cases a universal basic income offers more
freedom and security for the money. They also discuss whether and how other
kinds of government assistance - for housing, education, health care, etc., as
well as social contribution programs like Social Security - might be combined
with a basic income.
Is it
feasible? Even if America were a functioning democracy rather than a
dysfunctional plutocracy, would there be enough money? V.V. propose, for
illustrative purposes, a funding level of 25 percent of average GDP - around
$1200 per month in the United States. On one side of the ledger, this would
replace the public assistance portion of the government's current social
welfare spending - a considerable saving. But on the other side, it would - if
financed solely by a flat tax on labor income, and without taking into account
likely improvements in productivity and human capital that would eventually
result from a basic income - entail marginal tax rates somewhere between 60 and
80 percent.
Is that
the end of the story, the graveyard of our noble hope? Not quite. There are
several other possible - indeed socially beneficial - ways of raising revenue
besides taxing labor income. Before even mentioning them, though, one should
note an elementary fact about taxes. As a famous social parasite once remarked
(a sentiment echoed by another social parasite during a recent presidential
campaign debate): "Only the little people pay taxes." Tax evasion - primarily
by those who can afford to hire expensive tax lawyers - costs hundreds of
billions of dollars in lost tax revenues each year, and an estimated $20
trillion is held offshore for purposes of tax evasion. In a rational world, the
costly and destructive Global War on Terror would be replaced by a Global War
on Tax Evasion.
Even
before that happy day, much progress can be made simply by holding President
Trump to his campaign promise to eliminate the carried-interest deduction, a
$250 billion/year gift to hedge fund managers, and more generally by taxing
capital income at the same rate as labor income. Since the top 0.1 percent of
American households receive half of all capital gains, there can be no reason
for taxing them at a substantially lower rate than the median wage earner,
except a fanatical devotion to increasing the income of the fabulously wealthy,
a compulsion one might call Republicans' Disease.
Other
possible sources of revenue discussed by V.V. include user fees on scarce
resources like land, the atmosphere, and the broadcast spectrum; a "Tobin tax"
on financial transactions; and consumption and value-added taxes. They mention
only in passing possible reductions in military expenditures, but there are
large savings to be looked for from closing some of our nearly one thousand
foreign military bases and cancelling unnecessary weapons programs, above all
the mind-bogglingly expensive F-35 Joint Strike Fighter.
******************
Convalescence
from large-scale social pathologies like plutocracy is bound to be gradual.
Barring a miraculously rapid disappearance of Republicans' Disease, a universal
basic income will have to be approached by stages. Essentially this means
compromising on funding levels, funding range, or obligation to work. After further
technical but, again, lucid discussion, V.V. settle on two options: in
societies where the obstacles to a basic income are mainly political, a negative
income tax, which appears to base assistance on virtuous behavior, i.e.,
participation in the labor market; and in societies where the chief obstacles
are economic, a partial universal income, starting low and perhaps increasing
along with average productivity.
We can,
of course, start anywhere - "if only we had the courage," as Luther put it. It
hardly matters where or how. What matters - what will lift the heart of every
reader of Basic Income - is that Van
Parijs and Vanderborght have enlisted the rigor and scruple of first-rate
social science in the service of a generous social vision that is at least as
old as Saint Ambrose and as up-to-date as Pope Francis. Our sensible and humane
descendants - they are bound to be sensible and humane, since humanity would
otherwise have long since succumbed to nuclear or environmental catastrophe - will
doubtless wonder, with the easy impatience of posterity, what we were waiting
for. They may, in fairness to us, decide that we were waiting for books like
this.